Войти Регистрация

Docx

  • Рефераты
  • Дипломные работы
  • Прочее
    • Презентации
    • Рефераты
    • Курсовые работы
    • Дипломные работы
    • Диссертациии
    • Образовательные программы
    • Инфографика
    • Книги
    • Тесты

Информация о документе

Цена 12000UZS
Размер 180.6KB
Покупки 0
Дата загрузки 16 Апрель 2024
Расширение docx
Раздел Курсовые работы
Предмет Английский язык

Продавец

Bohodir Jalolov

The syntax nominalization

Купить
THE MINISTRY OF HIGHER EDUCATION SCIENCE AND
INNOVATIONS OF THE REPUBLIC OF UZBEKISTAN
SAMARKAND STATE  INSTITUTE  OF FOREIGN LANGUAGES
FACULTY OF  _____________________________
COURSE PAPER
THEME:   THE SYNTAX NOMINALIZATION CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION ....................................................................................................... 3
CHAPTER I. NOMINALIZATIONS IN SYNTACTIC THEORY ........................... 5
1.1 The types of nominalization linguistics ................................................................ 5
1.2 The role of nominalization .................................................................................. 17
Conclusion on chapter I ............................................................................................ 21
CHAPTER   II.   THE   MORPHOLOGY   OF   NOMINALIZATIONS   AND   THE
SYNTAX ................................................................................................................... 22
2.1 The classification of nominalization ................................................................... 22
2.2 The process of nominalization ............................................................................ 28
Conclusion on chapter II. .......................................................................................... 32
CONCLUSION ......................................................................................................... 33
REFERENCE ............................................................................................................ 35 INTRODUCTION
We   should   pay   great   attention   to   the   development   of   relations   with   foreign
writers,   the   experience   of   translating   and   publishing   the   best   examples   of   world
literature.   “As   a   result   of   the   reforms   carried   out   by   our   President,   almost   all
centuriesof world literature, including Shakespeare, have been translated into Uzbek,
and his comedies and tragedies have been staged in theaters [1, 3].
Nominalizations   are  nouns   that   are  morphologically  derived   from   expressions
(base   expressions)   of   possibly   other   syntactic   categories.   Nominalizations   present
major   challenges   for   semantics.   Nominalizations   involve   the   interface   of   semantics
with   morphosyntax   and   the   particular   issues   for   compositional   semantics   that   this
entails,   such   as   the   question   of   how   the   argument   structure   of   the   nominalization
relates   to   that   of   the   base   expression.   Moreover,   given   that   nominalizations   may
denote objects that are not already part of the semantics of the base expression, they
pose   particular   challenges   for   ontology,   raising   the   question   of   how   the   objects
denoted by the nominalization relate to the meaning of the base expression.
Nominalizations   have   also   played   a   major   role   in   philosophy,   and   in   fact   the
linguistic   study   of   nominalizations   may   shed   light   on   a   range   of   philosophical
debates.   Various   types   of   nominalizations   appear   to   stand   for   abstract   objects   or
highly   derivative   or   minor   entities   of   some   sort,   and   philosophers   have   often   made
use   of   nominalizations   for   the   purpose   of   a   philosophical   argument.   Obviously,   the
study   of   nominalizations   can   be   illuminating   as   regards   the   nature   of   the   abstract,
derivative, or minor entities that nominalizations are taken to denote, and as regards
the ontological operations that serve to introduce such objects,
The actuality of the course work: 
This   aims   of   the   course   work   is   to   investigate   the   nominalization   as   from
theoretical point of view, so from practical, and define the use of nominalization, its
syntactic functions. Moreover to give general definition of the nominalization
3 The subject and object of the course work. The object  of the course work is
that, in practical part I observed the information that was given in theoretical part and
showed their usage in tables and slides. The  subject  of my course paper is the syntax
nominalization.
The practical and theoretical value of the course work:
Theoretical   value   is   that   I   investigated   the   viewpoint   of   different   scholars
about the nominalization.
Practical value  is that having observed all the information, I showed the usage
of nominalization in tables and slides.
The task of investigation:
- To give general information about the nominalization.
- To dwell on the classification of the nominalization.
- To dwell on the question of nominalization.
The   scientific   novelty   of   the   work   is   scientific   analysis   of   the   information
sources   and   references,   description,   comparative   analysis   and   interpretation   of
sources, conceptual analysis of the literature, synthesis, study, content-analysis.
The structure of the course work. The research consists of an introduction,
2 chapters, a conclusion and a list of references and consists of 36 pages.
4 CHAPTER  I.  NOMINALIZATIONS IN SYNTACTIC THEORY
1.1 The types of nominalization linguistics
Nominalizations are nouns that are morphologically derived from an expression
of   another   category,   or   another   noun.   Thus,   driver   is   a   deverbal   nominalization
derived from the verb drive, thought a deverbal nominalization derived from the verb
think, happiness a deadjectival nominalization derived from the adjective happy, and
motherhood a nominalization derived from the noun mother. Also numerals like eight
are generally  taken to  be nominalizations  of   adjectives  when  appearing in  argument
position rather than in modifier or quantifier position. There are cases where it is not
clear   whether   the   noun   is   derived   from   the   verb   or   vice   versa,   for   example   need
(section 4). Moreover, there is the view of distributive morphology [2,9], according to
which the lexicon just contains category-less roots and both the base expression and
the nominalization may be obtained from the same root.
There   are   also   derivative   uses   of   the   term   “nominalization,”   especially   in   the
philosophical   literature.   Philosophers   sometimes   call   expressions   “nominalizations”
even if  they do not involve a morphological process  of  nominalization, for example
that-clauses;   that-clauses,   when   appearing   in   argument   position,   are   considered
nominalizations   of   sentences:   they   act   as   referential   terms   standing   for   an   object
obtained   from   the   meaning   of   a   sentence   (a   proposition).     Complex   NPs   with   that-
clauses  such as the fact  that  S are another  example. “Nominalization” has also  been
used   as   a   purely   semantic   term,  in   application  to   expressions   (or   uses   of   them)   that
appear to involve the very same semantic operation as is involved in the semantics of
particular   types   of   morphosyntactic   nominalization.   Thus,   quantifiers   such   as
something, everything, and nothing have been argued to range over the same things as
are semantic values of deverbal or deadjectival nominalizations, and in that sense are
nominalizing quantifiers [3,534]. 
Morphosyntactic issues
5 A   significant   part   of   the   semantic   literature   on   nominalization   is   devoted   to
questions   of   how   nominalizations   relate   to   the   argument   structure   of   the   base
expression, for example the question which argument position of the base expression
a   nominalization   can   pick   up   as   its   referential   (external)   position   and   whether   the
nominalization   preserves   the   other   argument   positions   of   the   base   expression.   In
addition, there is a focus in the linguistic literature on polysemies often displayed by
nominalizations, in particular result nominalizations such as destruction or building (I
will   come   back   to   the   issue   of   polysemies   of   nominalizations.   The   present   chapter
will instead focus on the semantics of nominalizations of what Montague would call
“philosophical   entities,”   such   as   nominalizations   standing   for   events,   facts,   and
tropes.   Against   that   background,   it   will   present   a   case   study   of   nominalizations   of
modal predicates, which have hardly received any attention in the linguistic literature.
Philosophical issues. Nominalizations play a significant role in philosophy and
have   been   used   as   important   tools   in   philosophical   theorizing.   Nominalizations   can
serve   to   form   terms   standing   for   philosophically   interesting   categories   of   objects,
abstract   objects   such   as   properties,   relations,   and   propositions,   as   well   as   concrete
objects   of   the   sort   of   events   and   tropes   (particularized   properties).   Thus,
nominalizations have played a major role in discussions in metaphysics, in particular
in relation to questions about the existence and nature of abstract objects, events, and
tropes.
Nominalizations have played a major role in the debate as to whether there are
universals   or   properties.   A   common   view   is   that   adjective   nominalizations   such   as
wisdom   stand   for   properties.   This   raises   the   question   of   whether   properties   are
ontologically real or derivative, introduced by the use of the expression itself. But the
view   that   adjective   nominalizations   stand   for   properties   has   itself   been   challenged.
When occurring in NPs of the sort Socrates’ wisdom, adjective nominalizations have
generally   been   taken   to   stand   for   tropes   or   particularized   properties,   rather   than
properties   acting   as   universals.   This   view   can   be   traced   to   Aristotle   and   has   been
6 taken   for   granted   throughout   most   of   medieval   and   modern   philosophy.   Even   when
adjective nominalizations occur as bare nouns (as in wisdom is rare), their function of
referring to properties has been questioned. On a par with nouns such as giraffes and
water,   bare   adjective   nominalizations   act   like   kind   terms   in   the   sense   of   Carlson,
displaying   different   properties   from   explicit   property-referring   terms   (such   as   the
property   of   being   wise).   Kinds   as   semantic   values   of   bare   mass   nouns   or   plurals   in
turn   may   be   viewed   as   pluralities   of   concrete   entities,   rather   than   as   single   abstract
objects [3,534]. The philosophical literature generally does not address the question of
how   the   meaning   of   the   nominalization   relates   to   the   adjective.   Event
nominalizations,   as   opposed   to   deadjectival   trope   nominalizations,   have   been
discussed   only   much   more   recently   in   philosophy,   in   particular   in   connection   with
Davidson’s view of events as primitive entities that also serve as implicit arguments
of eventive verbs. According to that view, the verb walk takes an event of walking as
an   implicit   argument   and   the   nominalization   walk   serves   to   make   reference   to   an
event   in   an   NP   like   John’s   walk.   The   Davidsonian   view   of   events   has   had   an
enormous   influence   in   linguistic   semantics,   and   almost   every   linguistic   account   of
deverbal nominalizations takes it for granted.
Strategies for introducing objects with nominalizations
Given   the   view   on   which   nominalizations   are   derived   from   base   expressions,
there are three ways in which the nominalization could obtain its semantic value:
1. by picking up an argument of the base expression,
2. by  introducing  an   object   by  abstraction   from   the   meaning   or   use   of   the
base expression,
3. by   mapping   an   argument   of   the   base   expression   to   a   closely   related
object.
We   will   see   that   all   three   strategies   are   involved   in   actual   types   of
nominalizations.   Strategy   1   is   involved   in   the   semantics   of   event   and   trope
nominalizations;   strategy   2   is   involved   in   fact   nominalizations   and   certain
7 nominalizations   of   modal   predicates;   strategy   3   is   involved   in   nominalizations   of
(non-stative) attitude verbs.
Picking up an argument of the base expression: Davidsonian event semantics
Nominalizations   are   nouns   that   are   derived   from   an   expression   (the   base
expression) of a possibly different category, such as a verb or an adjective. Thus the
nominalization   laughter   is   derived   from   the   verb   laugh   and   can   serve   to   form   the
referential term John’s laughter, referring to an event. The nominalization happiness
is derived from the adjective happy, and can serve to form the referential term John’s
happiness, referring to a trope or particularized property, that is, the manifestation of
happiness   in   John.   In   a   derivative   sense,   also   nominal   constructions   obtained   from
sentences are called nominalizations, such as the fact that John is happy, which is in a
way derived from the sentence John is happy.
Nominalizations obviously  have a semantics  that  is  related to that  of  the base
expression   and   so   should   have   a   meaning   that   is   obtainable   from   –   or   at   least
systematically related to – that of the base expression. For some nominalizations this
is straightforward; for example, agent nominalizations such as driver stand for entities
that are arguments of the base expression. But for nominalizations that are event and
trope   nominalizations   the   relation   to   the   meaning   of   the   base   expression   is   less
obvious.   Such   nominalizations   appear   to   introduce   “new”   entities   into   the   semantic
structure   of   sentences,   entities   that   would   not   be   part   of   the   semantic   structure   of
sentences   without   the   nominalization   and   whose   ontological   status   may   appear
problematic.
There   are   different   accounts   as   to   how   to   derive   the   meaning   of   a
nominalization   from   that   of   the   base   expression.   For   event   nominalizations   derived
from   verbs   such   as   laughter,   walk,   or   scream   as   well   as   adjective   nominalizations
such as wisdom  or happiness  one strategy by which this can be achieved is that the
nominalization  picks   up   an   implicit   argument   of   the   base   expression.   In  the   case   of
event nominalizations, this would be the implicit Davidsonian event argument of the
8 verb.   In   the   case   of   adjective   nominalizations,   this   would   be   an   implicit   trope
argument   of   the   adjective   (a   manifestation   of   wisdom   in   the   case   of   the
nominalization wisdom). The Davidsonian account of event nominalizations is due to
Higginbotham’s   development   of   Davidson’s   semantics   of   adverbials.   According   to
Davidsonian   event   semantics,   events   act   as   implicit   arguments   of   verbs,   and
adverbials are predicates of the implicit event argument of the verb.
The semantic status of events as implicit arguments of verbs goes along with a
particular   view   about   the   ontology   of   events,   on   which   events   are   primitive   entities
not to be defined in terms of objects, properties, and times. This means that predicates
with different meanings can be used to describe one and the same event. Events thus
are   not   conceived   as   entities   strictly   dependent   on   the   content   of   a   (canonical)
description, say composed of the meaning of the verb and its arguments.
Given   Davidsonian   event   semantics,   NPs   with   a   deverbal   nominalization   as
head   such   as   John’s   walk   can   be   given   a   straightforward   semantics   on   which   they
pick up the implicit event argument of the verb as their referent [4,95].
The   implicit   event   argument   of   the   verb   will   be   the   very   same   event   as   is
described by the event nominalization.5
Given the Davidsonian account, it is clear why the same expressions that act as
adverbials generally are able to act as predicates or adjectival modifiers of the event
nominalization of the verb.
The   Davidsonian   account   of   event   nominalizations   allows   a   rather
straightforward   extension   to   the   semantics   of   nominalizations   of   adjectives.   This,
though, requires   an enrichment   of   the ontology  of   natural   language  so  as  to include
tropes   besides   events.   While   this   view   was   more   recently  defended   in  Moltmann,   it
was   in   fact   also   the   standard   view   about   adjective   nominalizations   throughout   the
philosophical   literature   on   tropes.   It   is   a   view   that   goes   back   to   Aristotle   and   was
common   throughout   the   Aristotelian   tradition   in   medieval   and   early   modern
philosophy. Also in contemporary metaphysics, philosophers generally use adjectival
9 nominalizations   when   giving   examples   of   tropes.   Tropes     are   “particularized
properties,”   that   is,   concrete   manifestations   of   properties   in   objects.   They   are   not
properties   as   universals,   but   rather   properties   as   particulars,   dependent   on  particular
objects as their bearers.
Adjectives, to an extent, exhibit the very same alternation of expressions acting
both   as   modifiers   of   the   adjective   and   as   predicates   (or   adjectival   modifiers)   of   the
adjective nominalization. 
Mary’s   happiness   stands   for   the   particular   way   happiness   manifests   itself   in
Mary, an entity which is also an implicit argument of happy. Mary’s paleness stands
for   the   particular   manifestation   of   paleness   in   Mary,   which   is   also   an   implicit
argument of pale.
Why   should   the   implicit   argument   of   an   adjective   be   a   trope,   rather   than   a
state?   This   in   turn   raises   the   question,   what   are   states,   in   the   context   of   natural
language   ontology?   That   is,   how   are   our   intuitions   about   states   reflected   in   natural
language? States are certainly the sorts of things we refer to with terms like the state
of   Mary’s   being   happy   as   well   as   simply   the   gerund   Mary’s   being   happy.   States   in
that   sense   have   different   properties   from   the   entities   that   NPs   with   adjective
nominalizations   stand   for,   such   as   Mary’s   happiness.   For   example,   “Mary’s   being
happy” cannot be profound and “Mary’s being pale” cannot be extreme. By contrast,
such   properties   are   among   the   sorts   of   properties   that   “Mary’s   happiness”   and
“Mary’s paleness” can have. Tropes involve a particular manifestation of the property
in question whereas states just consist in an individual having that property.
Here max is a suitable maximality operator. Since there may be various tropes
of happiness of Mary at a period of time, the definite NP Mary’s happiness is taken to
stand for the maximal trope of happiness of Mary at that time, to ensure uniqueness.
Davidsonian   event   semantics   has   been   enormously   influential   in   linguistic
semantics,   and,   going   along   with   it,   the   Davidsonian   account   of   event
nominalizations. However, there is an alternative approach to the semantics of event
10 nominalizations,   based   on   Kim’s   conception   of   events.   What   has   sometimes   been
objected  to in the  Davidsonian  semantics  of  events  is  that   it  fails  to account  for   the
intuition   that   only   a   sentence   with   an   explicit   event-referring   term   such   as   (3b)   is
about an event; a sentence containing just a verb describing an event such as (3a) is
only about an agent, John, and not about an event. 
Introducing a referent by abstraction: Kimean event semantics
On the second strategy, a nominalization introduces a new entity on the basis of
the   meaning   of   the   base   expression,   in   addition   to   perhaps   further   expressions   or
entities.   This   can   be   called   the   “Kimian   account”   of   nominalizations,   since   it   goes
along   naturally   with   the   way   Kim   conceived   of   events,   as   entities   obtained   from   a
property, an object, and a time.
While   the   Kimian   account,   as   we   will   see,   appears   unsuitable   for   event
nominalizations, it will have an application to one kind of nominalization of a modal
predicate, namely possibility.
The Kimian account of event nominalizations matches a view on which events
are  introduced  into  the  semantic  structure  of   a  sentence   generally  only  by  means  of
nominalizations   (underived   event   nouns   such   as   fire,   war,   or   noise   would   be
exceptions).   Events   then   are   conceived   as   entities   that   strictly   depend   on   an
individual,   a   property,   and   a   time.   Kim’s   account   of   events   then   consists   in   the
following statement of existence and identity conditions for events:
Kim’s   account   of   events   does   not   explicitly   define   events   in   terms   of   a
property, an object, and a time. Rather the account consists in an implicit definition of
events, stating their existence and identity conditions in terms of an object, a property,
and a time. Kim’s account in fact introduces events by a form of Fregean abstraction.
Given   Kim’s   ontological   account   of   events,   the   semantics   of   event
nominalizations   appears   straightforward,   as   below,   where   the   denotation   of   walk,
[walk], is taken to be the one-place property of walking:
11 The   availability   of   event-characterizing   properties   conveyed   by   an   event
description would distinguish descriptions of events from explicit fact descriptions of
the sort the fact that S. Whereas adjective modifiers of event nominalizations may just
be event-characterizing, all of the content of a sentence S in a fact description of the
sort the fact that S must be fact-constitutive. 
Events are relatively independent of the description used to refer to them. Facts,
by contrast, are entirely reflected in the meaning of explicit fact-referring terms of the
sort the fact.
The difference in description, however, won’t account for various differences in
properties between events and facts. An object introduced by Fregean abstraction has
just those properties specified by the method of introduction. Thus, given (8), events
have   identity   conditions   and   existence   conditions   relative   to   a   time,   but   they   won’t
have other intrinsic properties. (They may, though, act as objects of mental attitudes.)
This means in particular that events won’t have a part structure, won’t have a spatial
location,  won’t   enter   causal   relations,   won’t   act   as   objects   of   perception,   and  won’t
have  properties   of   intensity   or  other  measurable   properties.   This  of  course  is   highly
counterintuitive.   It   is   certainly   part   of   our   notion   of   an   event   for   an   event   to   have
those properties. By contrast, though, it is part of our notion of a (non-worldly) fact to
lack those properties.
These   differences   between   events   and   facts   are   linguistically   well   reflected,
namely   in   the   applicability   of   part-related   constructions   such   as   partitive   part   of   as
well as predicates of concreteness of various sorts, as seen below:
The   main   objection   to   Kim’s   account   of   events   has   been   that   it   assimilates
events to facts. Note that any property, however unspecific or logically complex, can,
for   Kim,   be   event-constitutive.   Any   predicate   expressing   a   nonnatural   or
indeterminate   property,   any   explicitly   or   implicitly   quantified   predicate,   and   any
negated or disjunctive predicate can, on Kim’s account, individuate an event (together
with   an   individual   and   a   time).   But   this   is   characteristic   of   (non-worldly)   facts,   not
12 events.  Nonspecific properties,  negation, disjunction, and  quantification can  be fact-
constitutive, but generally not event-constitutive. Events as concrete objects must be
maximally   specific   or   at   least   grounded   in   specific   properties   (Moltmann   2007;
2013a; 2013b; 2019b).
One   might   try   to   account   for   the   groundedness   of   events   by   imposing   the
restriction that events can be constituted only by fully determinate properties or rather
property changes. However, if events are introduced by abstraction, even if based on
such specific property changes, they will still lack the typical event properties. That is
because   the   only   properties   they   can   have   are   those   that   come   with   the   strategy   of
their introduction.
Moreover,   if   events   are   “introduced”   into   the   semantic   structure   of   sentences
only by nominalizations, then the descriptive content of a nominalization would have
to be fully event-constitutive, but this is generally not the case.
However Kim’s account is suited as an account of fact nominalizations, that is,
nominalizations   of   the   sort   the   fact   that   S,   for   a   true   sentence   S.   These   are
nominalizations standing for facts as non-worldly facts, that is, facts that correspond
to   true   propositions   and   are   tied   to   the   content   of   the   fact   description   itself.   More
precisely, (8) gives a semantic account of a simple fact description of the sort the fact
that Mary is happy today, introducing a fact on the basis  of  an individual  (Mary), a
property (happiness), and a time (the time of today).
Mapping an argument of the base expression to a closely related object: product
nominalizations and attitudinal-object nominalizations
The   Davidsonian   account   of   event   nominalizations   appears   to   apply   well   to
verbs describing physical events. However, it does not apply well to nominalizations
derived   from   attitude   verbs   such   as   think,   decide,   claim,   and   request.   Such   verbs
display a distinction between two sorts of deverbal nominalizations that display sharp
semantic   differences   (and   not   just   in   English):   nominalizations   of   the   sort   thought,
decision, claim, and request on the one hand and gerunds such as thinking, deciding,
13 claiming,   and   requesting   on   the   other   hand.13   This   is   a   distinction   that   the   Polish
early analytic philosopher Twardowski introduced as the distinction between actions
and what he called “products.” According to that distinction, nominalizations such as
thought, decision, claim, and request  describe non-enduring “products” of actions of
thinking, judging, claiming, and requesting, the actions described by the base verbs.
By   contrast,   gerunds   such   as   thinking,   judging,   deciding,   claiming,   requesting,   and
promising   describe   actions,   the   very   same   entities   described   by   the   base   verbs.   The
non-enduring products of actions are as concrete and particular as the actions and in
fact,   according   to   Twardowski   [5,132],   spatiotemporally   coincident   with   them.   The
notion of a product is closely related to that of a modal object, and so it is appropriate
to   elaborate   on   the   action–product   distinction   as   introduced   by   Twardowski   and
further elaborated in Moltmann.
Actions   and   products   differ   fundamentally   in   their   properties.   Most
importantly, as Twardowski emphasizes, only products and not actions may bear truth
conditions or, more generally, satisfaction conditions.
Note   that   the   applicability   of   predicates   of   satisfaction   makes   clear   that
products cannot be identified with propositions, since propositions cannot be fulfilled,
implemented,   executed,   kept,   or   broken.   Rather   products   are   entities   sui   generis,
sharing   some   similarities   with   both   propositions   and   events,   but   are   not   to   be
identified with either of them [6,127].
Products differ from actions furthermore in entering relations of exact similarity
just on the basis of being the same in content, provided they involve the same force
and possibly physical manifestation.
While   the   ability   of   products   to   have   truth   or   satisfaction   conditions   and   to
enter similarity relations based on a shared content can be attributed to Twardowski,
there   is   another   important   difference   between   actions   and   products   not   noted   by
Twardowski and that concerns part whole relations. The part structure of products is
strictly   based   on   partial   content,   not   the   temporal   parts   (sub-events)   an   act   would
14 have. A part of a thought, a belief, or a decision is a partial content. By contrast, the
part   structure   of   actions   is   that   of   events,   consisting   of   temporal   parts.   Parts   of
products  generally  are distinct  from   the parts  of  the  actions.  Part   of   John’s  decision
cannot   be   part   of   the   action   of   deciding.   Part   of   John’s   claim   cannot   be   part   of   the
speech act. Part of John’s promise cannot be part of John’s act of promising.
There are further properties distinguishing actions and products. Only products
not actions can enter causal relations on the basis of content; that is, only products can
have causal effects in virtue of their content. John’s claim may cause astonishment or
puzzlement in virtue of its content, but not so for John’s act of claiming.
John’s remark may trigger a lot of comments in virtue of its content, but not so
for John’s making a remark. John’s promise may have made Mary happy in virtue of
its   content,   but   not   so   for   John’s   act   of   promising.   Acts,   of   course,   enter   causal
relations, but not that of content-based causation.
Actions  and  products  also  differ   in properties  relating  to  the  understanding  of
their   associated   content.   Understanding   a   claim   or   request   means   something   quite
different from understanding an act of claiming or requesting. Only the former relates
to the content of the product, not the latter.
Related   to   properties   of   content-based   causation   and   understanding   are
properties of content-based evaluation. Attitudinal objects are evaluated with respect
to both their content and force, but not so for actions. A thought being interesting is
something   quite   different   from   the   act   of   thinking   being   interesting.   It   is   also
something different  from  an abstract  proposition  being interesting.  Similarly, John’s
thought   process   may   be   unusual,   without   his   thought   or   the   corresponding   abstract
proposition being unusual.
Thus,   an   ontological   distinction   must   be   made   between   cognitive   or
illocutionary   acts   and   their   non-enduring   products.   For   the   semantics   of
nominalizations this means that non-gerundive nominalizations of psychological  and
illocutionary verbs do not just pick up the implicit event argument of the verb. Rather
15 their semantics will be more complex involving a function mapping an implicit event
argument onto its non-enduring product. 
The action  product  distinction  does not  apply to stative  attitude verbs  such  as
believe, intend, fear, and hope. Mental states do not, at least not generally, come with
products.   Yet   the   entities   that   the   nominalizations   of   stative   attitude   verbs   describe,
such   as   belief,   intention,   fear,   hope,   display   the   very   same   characteristic   types   of
properties   as   cognitive   or   illocutionary   products.   In   particular,   they   have   truth   or
satisfaction conditions:
Nominalizations   of   stative   attitude   verbs   stand   for   entities   that   share   the
characteristic types of properties of cognitive and illocutionary products, but are not
themselves   products   of   acts.   This   motivates   the   broader   category   of   what   I   call
attitudinal   objects,   which   comprises   both   cognitive   and   illocutionary   objects   and
state-like entities such as beliefs and intentions (Moltmann 2013b; 2017a). Attitudinal
objects   thus   form   an   ontological   category   of   concrete   particulars   that   have   content-
related   properties   (having   satisfaction   conditions,   entering   similarity   relations   based
on   sameness   of   content,   and   having   a   part   structure   based   on   partial   content).   The
term   attitudinal-object   nominalization   should   hence   replace   the   more   narrow   term
product nominalization, for nominalizations of attitude verbs.
Thus,   nominalizations   of   verbs   and   adjectives   in   English   consist   in   event
nominalizations   and   trope   nominalizations,   as   well   as   attitudinal-object
nominalizations,   and   they   involve   an   ontology   of   events,   tropes,   and   attitudinal
objects. They manifest two ways for a nominalization to obtain its referent, by picking
up an implicit argument of the base expression and by mapping such an argument to a
closely related object.
16 1.2  The role of nominalization
Nominalization   serves   to   simplify   complex   ideas   by   reducing   the   number   of
words needed to convey them. This is especially important in scientific writing, where
clarity and precision are critical. Nominalized phrases such as "the analysis of data" or
"the   investigation   of   phenomena"   allow   writers   to   express   complex   concepts   in   a
single   word   or   phrase.   This   not   only  makes   sentences   shorter   and  more   concise   but
also helps readers understand the main idea more easily.
Another   advantage   of   nominalization   is   that   it   allows   writers   to   focus   on   the
subject matter rather than individual actions or events. For example, instead of writing
"we   conducted   experiments,"   a   writer   could   use   "experimental   procedures   were
employed."   This   phrasing   emphasizes   the   methods   used   rather   than   the   individuals
performing them, which can be important when conducting research.
Nominalization is a linguistic process that transforms a verb or an adjective into
a noun. This process involves the addition of suffixes to verbs, such as -tion, -ment,
and -ance. Nominalization is a common feature of academic writing and it is used to
create abstract nouns that encapsulate complex ideas.
One   example   of   nominalization   can   be   seen   in   the   following   sentence:   "The
government's   decision   to  increase   taxes   was   met   with   widespread   criticism."   In   this
sentence,   "decision"   is   a  nominalized   form   of   the  verb   "decide."   By   using   the  noun
form, the writer is able to convey a complex idea in a more concise manner.
Another   example   can   be   seen   in   the   sentence:   "The   construction   of   new
buildings in downtown areas has led to increased traffic congestion." In this sentence,
"construction"   is   a   nominalized   form   of   the   verb   "construct."   Again,   by   using   the
noun form, the writer is able to convey a complex idea more succinctly.
Nominalization can also be used to create abstract  nouns from  adjectives. For
example, "happiness" is a nominalized form of the adjective "happy," while "strength"
is   a   nominalized   form   of   the   adjective   "strong."   However,   the   overuse   of
nominalizations   can   have   negative   impacts   on   academic   writing.   Excessive
17 nominalizations  can  obscure  meaning by  creating  longer  sentences  that   readers  may
find challenging to comprehend quickly. Additionally, overuse may lead to ambiguity
in sentences as noun-based phrases tend to lack verb tenses which would help define
tense-related meanings.  Nominalization is a crucial  tool  for  academic  writing, but  it
should   be   used   judiciously.   The   technique   enables   writers   to   convey   complex   ideas
and   concepts   accurately   while   maintaining   a   formal   tone.   However,   writers   must
ensure   that   they   do   not   overuse   nominalization   in   their   writing,   as   this   can   lead   to
confusion and ambiguity.
One   of   the   most   striking   linguistic   features   of   legal   writing   is   the   use   of
complex   heavily   postmodified   nominal   phrases.   The   two   following   examples   are
taken from Wills Act, 1970 and a Seller – Buyer contract, 1998. The nominal phrases
are shown in square brackets. 
Chomsky believes that “nominalisation is a process by which a verb phrase is
transformed   into   a   nominal”.   A   similar   attitude   to   nominalisation   is   presented   by
Quirk who considers nominalisation a process of turning a verb or an adjective into a
noun. Halliday [7] describes nominalisation more generally – as any element or group
that   can   function   as   a   noun   or   a   noun   group.   Mathews   defines   nominalisation
similarly   to   Halliday   –   as   “any   process   by   which   either   a   noun   or   a   syntactic   unit
functioning as a noun phrase is derived from any other kind of unit”. Bhatia refers to
it   as   “the   third   type   of   complex   nominal   phrases   that   is   conventionally   called
nominalisation, and is overwhelmingly used in legislative provisions”. 
The creators of the texts do not take into consideration an aesthetic viewpoint.
From   the point   of   view of  creators  nominalisation  can  be understood  as  a  means  of
condensation and clarity. In my view the high occurrence of nominal phrases causes a
certain degree of ambiguity in legal text interpretation.  
The idea of determiners in grammar is quite new, and there is still some debate
about them whether or  not  they constitute a word class. Members of  the same  word
class behave in the same- they serve the same function in an utterance.  
18 Determiners are sometimes considered a weird word class because almost all its
members   (with   the   exception   of   articles)   belong   at   least   to  two   word   classes.   Many
words used as determiners can also be used as pronouns or as adverbs.  
As a closed word class  determiners have a certain function in language. They
“signal nouns in a variety of ways: they may define the relationship of the noun to the
speaker or listener (or reader); they may identify the noun as specific or general; they
may quantify it specifically or refer to quantity in general"[8]. “The determiner class
is   one   of   the   structure   classes   that   straddle   the   line   between   a   word   class   and   a
function.   On   the   one   hand,   our   most   common   determiners,   the   articles,   do   indeed
constitute   a   small,   closed   structure   class.   At   the   other   end   of   the   spectrum   are   the
possessive nouns, which function as determiners while retaining their membership in
the open class noun. In between are the subclasses of determiners that belong to the
closed pronoun class: Demonstrative, possessive, and indefinite pronouns all function
as   determiners;   and,   of   course,   as   pronouns   they   also   function   as   nominals   (in   fact,
'pronominal' would be a more accurate label than 'pronoun').
The investigation conducted into the legal texts confirmed a high frequency of
determiners in them. Their high occurrence is not unintentional and accidental. As it
has been mentioned nominalisation is a frequent phenomenon in legal writing. Every
nominal   phrase   found   in   the   analysed   legal   texts   starts   with   a   determiner.   The
determiner that accompanies a noun has an important role – it is a carrier of reference.
This paper does not deal with all determiners, the concentration will be put on
the demonstratives this, these, that and those. 
The   categorisation   of   this,   that,   these   and   those   has   been   complicated.   J.   C.
Nesfield in his Outline of English Grammar published in 1919 says that this and that
belong   to   demonstrative   pronouns.     He   does   not   mention   that   they   may   function   as
determiners.  
Later   in   Zandwort’s   Handbook   of   English   grammar   we   find   “There   are   four
demonstrative pronouns in common use this and that and their plural variations these
19 and those. This and these refer to what is near in space, time or conception, that and
those to what is farther off. He demonstrates also their temporal usage. This may refer
to what follows and that to what precedes”.   According to Greebaum and Quirk “the
demonstratives   this,   that,   these,   those   function   both   as   pronouns   and   demonstrative
determiners”. 
20 Conclusion on chapter I
In syntactic theory, nominalizations refer to the process in which a verb or an
adjective   is   turned   into   a   noun.   This   process   involves   morphological   and   syntactic
changes that  allow the word to function as a noun in a sentence.  One common way
that nominalizations are created is through the addition of suffixes. For example, the
verb   "analyze"   can   be   turned   into   the   noun   "analysis"   by   adding   the   suffix   "-sis."
Similarly, the adjective "active" can become the noun "activity" by adding the suffix
"-ity."
Nominalizations can also involve changes in word order or the addition of other
words   to   create   a   noun   phrase.   For   example,   the   verb   "run"   can   be   nominalized   by
changing   the   word   order   and   adding   a   determiner   and   an   adjective,   resulting   in   the
noun phrase "a quick run." The syntactic properties of nominalizations can differ from
their   base   verbs   or   adjectives.   For   example,   nominalizations   often   have   different
syntactic   roles   and   can   be   used   as   subjects,   objects,   or   complements   in   a   sentence.
They   may   also   require   different   syntactic   constructions   or   take   on   different
grammatical functions than their base forms. 
In   syntactic   analysis,   the   study   of   nominalizations   helps   to   understand   how
language structures can be transformed and how different parts of speech can interact.
It   also   helps   to   explain   how   nominalizations   contribute   to   sentence   structure   and
meaning..
21 CHAPTER II. THE MORPHOLOGY OF NOMINALIZATIONS AND
THE SYNTAX
2.1  The classification of nominalization
According to the classification of  nominalization raised by Halliday, there are
altogether   five   kinds   of   nominalization,   namely,   nominalization   of   process,
nominalization   of   quality,   nominalization   of   circumstance,   nominalization   of   relator
and nominalization of zero. Since nominalization not only involves the transformation
of grammatical classes, more importantly, it also contains the change of function. 
As   a   special   genre,   abstract   draws   a   lot   of   attention   among   researchers.   Day
defined   abstract   as   a   “highly   summarized   discourse   that   enable   readers   to   grasp   the
purpose,   methodology   and   main   results   of   a   paper   quickly   and   let   readers   evaluate
whether this paper is worth reading”. Chinese scholar Xu claimed that, “An abstract is
a   highly   condensed   form   of   a   longer   piece   of   writing   so   that   readers   can   know   the
main contents and scope of the thesis and decide whether it is necessary to read the
whole.   It   should   be   a   high   generalization   and   objective   description   without   any
subjective comments or explanation.” From these definitions, it can be seen that they
all thought that abstract is very important since it can help readers to understand the
overall content of a paper and get some useful points, so abstract has some essential
characteristics.   It   is   agreed   that   a   well-written   abstract   is   featured   by   conciseness,
objectivity and coherence. First, because abstract is a highly condensed discourse and
it   summarizes   the   major   points   of   a   paper,   thus   its   language   should   be   precise   and
concise, which means using fewer words to convey more information. Second, due to
the formality and scientificity of the academic papers, language in abstract should be
objective,   stating   facts   and   data   rather   than   subjective   opinions.   The   expressions   of
abstract   must   conform   to   features   of   scientific   and   technical   discourse   [10,31].
Finally, as a complete discourse, abstract should be logical and coherent. In order to
let readers understand the major points of the paper, expressions in abstract should be
linked logically and coherently [9,718].
22 Ant Conc and manual sorting are adopted in the present research for identifying
all   the   nominalizations.   File  view   tool   in   AntConc   is   used   to  check   different   use   of
five   types   of   nominalization   in   original   text,   hence,   the   collocating   patterns   of   each
type of nominalization can be identified, besides, with the assistance of Concordance
Tool,   frequencies   of   those   collocating   patterns   can   be   calculated   as   well.   Since   the
accuracy   of   identification   of   nominalization   can   not   be   guaranteed   by   only   using
AntConc,   so   manual   sorting   will   also   be   applied   to   identifying   five   types   of
nominalization. 
This   research   involves   three   procedures.   First,   two   separate   corpus   are
constructed, which includes 120 English abstracts from two Chinese journals and two
international   journals.   Second.   Finally,   this   study   will   use   specific   examples   to
analyze how Chinese and Western scholars use different methods to achieve features
of abstracts. From this part, some useful suggestions about how to use nominalization
properly and flexibly will be offered. 
As a highly concise summary of the full text, language used in abstracts should
be   concise   and   specific.   Thompson   proposed   that   one   important   feature   of   written
English is syntactic simplicity. Hence, abstracts undertake an important task, which is
to   express   abundant   information   as   much   as   possible   within   fewest   words.
Nominalization is one of the best  methods to condense information and increase the
conciseness of abstracts. After analyzing all the abstracts, it is found that both Chinese
and Western scholars prefer to use process and quality nominalizations to increase the
conciseness of abstracts. 
One of the powerful function of nominalization is to increase lexical density of
the   original   congruent   sentence,   in   this   way,   the   length   of   the   original   sentence   is
shortened and more space are left for more valuable information [11,430]. According
to the statistical results, it can be seen that process nominalization is frequently used
by Chinese and Western scholars to increase lexical density. 
23 Apart   from   process   nominalization,   quality   nominalization   can   achieve
conciseness   through   improving   economy.   Owing   to   the   written   and   formal   style   of
abstracts   [12,1221],   both   Chinese   and   Western   scholars   are   under   the   pressure   of
making   their   language   concise,   meanwhile,   informative.   Nominalization   is   an
effective   tool   which   can   help   writers   improving   economy   of   language,   moreover,
increasing the conciseness of abstracts. The following table presents some frequently
used quality nominalization by Chinese and Western scholars, 
Actually,   the   most   powerful   function   of   nominalization   is   to   downgrade
sentences to nominal groups through rank shift. Packing information into some noun
phrases   allows   writers   to   expand   semantic   meaning   of   nominlization   by   adding
modifiers   or   qualifiers.   Moreover,   through   rank   shift,   noun   phrases   or   clauses   are
replaced by clause complexes, therefore, writers can simplify the sentence structure,
condense the textual space [12,30]. So when expressing the same content, in terms of
conciseness,   metaphorical   expressions   are   superior   to   congruent   expressions.
Consequently,   language   will   be   more   perspicuous   and   succinct.   A   better
understanding of how this works can be gained from specific examples. 
3) On the basis of the findings, pedagogical implications are discussed.
4) The findings suggest that the development of L2 learners’ processing pattern
of the complex words is the transition from the decompositional processing route to
the whole word processing one.
From example , it can be found that there are two nominalizations, implications
and findings. If  the writer  uses  the congruent  form to express  this sentence, at lease
three   clauses   are   needed,   i.e.,   we   find   something,   the   findings   implicate   something,
and we discuss the implications. Apparently, this kind of expression is too wordy and
complex. Through nominalization, three clauses are rank shifted into a lower level, a
nominal form; in this way, the sentence is predigested and information is condensed.
As   a   result,   expressions   become   more   natural   and   easy   to   understand.   By   using
nominalization, the whole expression becomes more concise, and the interrelationship
24 between processes are clear. In example, this sentence is fairly long and contains a lot
of   lexical   items.   The   writer   uses   three   nominalization   findings,   development   and
transition   to   construct   a   very   simple   structure,   and   readers   can   easily   grasp   the
relationship   among   three   processes   in   this   sentence.   It   can   be   seen   that   using
nominalization makes sentence shorter and briefer. Through rank shift, noun phrases
are employed to convey the same meaning that is otherwise congruently expressed in
a   more   complex   structure.   In   this   way,   scholars   use   the   simplest   and   shortest
expressions   to   convey   the   most   important   meaning,   leaving   more   space   for   other
points.   On   the   whole,   abstract   are   characterized   by   the   use   of   the   briefest   words   to
express   the   richest   content,   and   they   contain   a   large   amount   of   information.
Nominalization   can   effectively   improve   the   lexical   density   and   conciseness   of
abstracts [13,81]. Using nominalization is conducive to the decrease of the number of
clauses, accommodating more information within the same space. 
Nominal forms usually possess the feature of static, by transforming a process
or quality into a noun, writers can state a fact and eliminate the subjectivity of their
expression. Through using of nominalization, the participant in the original action is
deleted,   weakened   or   hidden   as   modifiers   of   the   nominalization.   At   the   same   time,
nominalization usually is non-finite, and is therefore not forced to express tense and
mood.   Accordingly,   nominalizations   are   on   a   higher   level   of   abstraction   and   can
enhance the objectivity of abstracts.  
Another function of process  nominalization is to anonymize the original  actor
of the sentence,  in this way, the sentence becomes a statement  without any personal
judgment,   the   whole   expression   seems   more   objective   and   formal   [14,51].   In
academic   genre,   subject   is   seldom   mentioned   in   the   sentence,   because   the   writer
intends   to   make   every   step   of   his   research   objective,   readers   can   believe   that   his
research does  not  involve any subjective  factor. For  the  sake of  avoiding using first
person pronoun as the subject of the sentence, writers use nominalization to hide the
original   actor   and   obscure   the   time   maker.   Because   when   using   nominalization   of
25 process,   writers   of   abstracts   need   not   to   take   tense   into   consideration,   they   only
displays   researches   process   and   results,   language   becomes   more   objective   to   some
extent.
Results   show   that   both   Chinese   and   Western   scholars   prefer   to   use
nominalizations   that   describe   research   processes   and   methodologies   to   hide   the
original   actor.   Such   as   evaluation,   if   the   writer   uses   sb   evaluate   sth,   it   seems   too
subjective, and such expression is seldom used in academic genre. So evaluation is in
conformity   with   the   requirement   of   academic   writing.   When   the   action   is   taken   by
writers themselves, they will choose to use nominal form to hide their identity for the
purpose   of   being   objective.   More   examples   are   given   to   explain   how   to   achieve
objectivity through the use of nominalization of process. 
All the nominalizations used in these sentences are transferred from their verbal
form, and they originally describe the research methodology or procedure, if writers
use   the   congruent   from,   an   actor   must   exist,   thus   the   expression   will   contain
subjective   factor.   By   using   nominalizations,   functions   of   original   actor   were
weakened, and only facts are presented. The focus of the sentence are shift from the
people   who   undertaken   the   research   to   the   researches.   Moreover,   process
nominalization   is   detached   from   the   limitation   of   tense   and   mood,   thus   the
descriptions can be used under any conditions. Process nominalization fulfills the task
of   enhancing   the   objectivity   of   abstracts.   Therefore,   both   Chinese   and   Western
scholars   frequently   employ   process   nominalization   to   weaken   their   influence   on
expressions, presenting a statement. 
Modality   can   express   speaker’s   proposition   and   attitude   effectively,   for   it   not
only can express speaker’s own willing, but also can state the speaker’s judgment and
evaluation   toward   an   event.   It   can   be   found   that   through   the   analysis   of   modality,
researchers can basically know the speaker’s judgment and attitude toward an event.
For example, 
26 The word capacity is the nominal form of the modal word can, it transfers the
modal meaning into “thing” which is hard to question. Thus it possesses the property
of   nouns,   which   is   “thingness”.   Writers   does   not   use   expression   like   sb   can   do
something, it sounds  too subjective, and readers may have doubts about its validity.
On the contrary, they applied a process nominalization, decorating their opinion as a
objective statement to highlight their statement. Thus it’s difficult for readers to judge
the   origin   of   the   modality,   they   have   to   take   the   modal   meaning   conveyed   by   this
process   nominalization   as   a   relatively   neutral   opinion,   actually,   the   speaker’s
subjective inclination is hidden behind the process nominalization. Moreover, process
nominalization   are   always   used   to   hide   the   modality   and   decrease   the   interpersonal
function   of   a   sentence.   Through   this   way,   the   origin   and   meaning   of   modality   are
omitted, make the audience lose the ability of evaluating and they can not question the
validity of the information. 
Hiding   personal   opinion.   In   abstracts,   all   the   statements   should   be   objective,
expressions   involving   subjective   judgment   should   be   avoided.   Under   most
circumstances,   adjectives   are   used   to   modify   things   and   add   author’s   evaluations,
however, in formal  text, adjectives  should be transferred  to nouns. With the help of
quality nominalization, personal judgments are replaced by objective illustration. 
27 2.2 The process of nominalization
Nominalization refers both to the process by which complex nouns are created
and to the complex nouns that are derived by that process. Nominalizations common
in the languages of the world include event/result nouns, personal or participant nouns
(agent, patient,  location, etc.),  as  well  as   collectives  and  abstracts.  It   is  common for
nominalizations to be highly polysemous.
Many   of   the   key   theoretical   debates   concerning   nominalization   arise   because
derived   nouns   exhibit   widespread   and  pervasive   polysemy.   For   example,   in  English
deverbal   nouns  formed   with  suffixes   like  -ing,  -ation,  -ment,  and   -al  are  ambiguous
between   readings   that   can   broadly   be   characterized   as   eventive   and   non-eventive.
Various   terms   have   been   proposed   in   the   literature   for   this   distinction,   including
Event versus Result, Process versus Result, and Event versus Referential.
With   the   eventive   reading,   the   nominalization   receives   roughly   the
interpretation of the corresponding sentence (The doctor examined the patient). With
the   non-eventive   interpretation,   a   variety   of   referential   readings   can   be   available,
depending on the verbal base of the nominalization:
Individual   nominalizations   can   express   both   eventive   and   referential   readings
and   often   are   amenable   to   several   different   referential   readings,   depending   on   the
syntactic contexts in which they are found:
Within the eventive nominalizations, Grimshaw makes an additional distinction
between   what   she   calls   complex   event   and   simple   event   nominal.   In   Grimshaw’s
terms, the complex event reading requires the nominalization to appear with the full
argument structure of the corresponding verb. In cases where full argument structure
is  absent,   Grimshaw  uses  the  term  “simple   event.”  Both  complex   and  simple  nouns
may have simple event interpretations, as the example in illustrates, but only derived
nominals may have complex event interpretations for Grimshaw.
In   effect,   Grimshaw’s   distinction   between   complex   event   reading   and   simple
event  reading refers to the syntactic context  of  the deverbal  noun, rather than to the
28 reading of the noun itself; in either the simple or complex event reading, the noun is
construed eventively.
Other types of nominalization also typically exhibit polysemy. For example, the
affix   -er   in   English   typically   forms   agent   nouns,   but   it   also   forms   instrument,
experiencer,   stimulus,   location,   means,   and   even   patient   nouns   as   well,   as   has   been
pointed out many times in the literature [15,1083]:
As Booij  [20,503] shows,  the roughly same  range of polysemy is available in
Dutch:
The suffix -ee in English is less prone to polysemy than -er, typically forming
animate patient nouns, but in some cases its referent is construed as an agent noun ,
and   in   some   cases   as   what   would   be   the   object   of   a   preposition   for   its   base   verb
(Barker, 1998):
Nouns   derived   with   the   affix   -er   in   English   are   also   argued   to   exhibit   a
distinction between an eventive reading and what is variously called in the literature a
non-eventive reading [16,310], a dispositional reading, or a dynamic reading [17,81].
With the eventive reading, an -er nominal like trimmer in a phrase like a trimmer of
hedges putatively must refer to someone who has actually participated in an event of
hedge-trimming. In a  compound like hedge-trimmer, however, the -er  nominal  need
not refer to an actual event, but can be interpreted dispositionally: a hedge-trimmer is
someone/something   that   has   the   disposition,   that   is,   the   ability   or   capacity,   to   trim
hedges, although he/she/it may never have actually trimmed a hedge. This reading, as
Cohen [19,103] points out, is one of dynamic modality, akin to the sense of can we
get in a sentence like:
Even collective and abstract nominalizers can display polysemy, although their
range of  readings  is  typically  less  broad than  the  other   nominalizers  (Lieber,  2016).
For   example,   the   suffix   –(e)ry,   which   frequently   forms   collectives   in   English
(jewelry), can sometimes form nouns that denote events (bribery), types of behavior
29 (clownery),   or   even   locations.   As   Lieber   documents,   it   is   the   norm   rather   than   the
exception for nominalizations to accommodate multiple readings.
Nominalization   lies   at   the   heart   of   the   ongoing   debate   between   syntactic   and
lexicalist analyses of word formation; central to this debate is the attempt to explain
the  pervasive   polysemy   described.   In  syntactic   analyses   of   nominalization,  different
readings of complex nouns are made to follow from their syntactic derivation, that is,
from some combination of argument structure, underlying syntactic structure, and the
operation of movement rules. Non-syntactic analyses of nominalization take a variety
of forms. Some rely on morphological rules that refer to argument structure, others on
lexical semantic representations, but all agree in denying that the different readings of
nominalizations are to be explained by their syntactic structure or by the operation of
syntactic rules.
The   first   treatment   of   nominalization   within   generative   theory,   Lees   (1960)
captures   the   relationship   between   the   sentence   and   the   nominalization   via
transformational rule.
In   the   earliest   forms   of   generative   theory,   transformational   rules   provided   the
only mechanism for expressing such semantic relationships. Transformations had the
power to rearrange constituents, build structure, and add morphology. The assumption
was   that   transformations   were   meaning-preserving   rules,   so   that   the   rearrangements
effected   by   the   rule   carried   the   eventive   reading   of   the   base   verb   over   to   the
nominalization.
Chomsky’s [18,221] article “Remarks on Nominalization” is considered to be a
watershed   in   the   analysis   of   nominalization.   Derived   nominals,   for   Chomsky,   are
complex   nouns   formed   with   affixes   like   -ation,   -ment,   -al,   and   -ure   in   English;   a
phrase   with   a   derived   nominal   such   as   that   displays   the   internal   syntax   of   a   noun
phrase.   What   would   be   the   subject   of   the   corresponding   sentence   appears   as   a
possessive   phrase,   the   sentential   object   appears   as   a   prepositional   phrase,   and
modification is obligatorily adjectival. Gerundive nominals are derived with -ing and
30 occur in noun phrases that have the internal syntax of sentences: the “object” of the -
ing nominal is a noun phrase rather than a prepositional phrase, and modifiers must be
adverbial.   Chomsky   distinguishes   a   third   category   as   well,   which   he   calls   mixed
nominalizations.   As   in   gerundives,   these   are   derived   with   the   -ing   affix,   but   like
derived   nominalizations   they   have   the   internal   syntax   of   noun   phrases   rather   than
sentences, requiring a post-nominal prepositional phrase and adjectival modification.
Chomsky   [18,221]     argues   that   derived   nominals   in   English   are   too
idiosyncratic   to   be   accounted   for   by   syntactic   rules.   Formally,   it   is   impossible   to
predict   whether   a   derived   nominal   will   exist,   and   if   it   does,   what   affix   it   will   take.
Derived   nominals   are   often   semantically   idiosyncratic.   Gerundive   nominals,   on   the
other   hand,   are   regular   enough   to  merit   a   syntactic   analysis:   every   verb  has   an   -ing
nominal   form   with  predictable   semantics.   Chomsky   does   not   himself   offer   a   formal
analysis of nominalization. He does, however, suggest  that a verb like refuse and its
nominalization   refusal   could   be   derived   from   a   single   lexical   entry   which   is
underlyingly neutral as to syntactic category, a suggestion that has been picked up in
subsequent  syntactic analyses \. Most  significantly, Chomsky’s arguments excluding
derived nominals from syntactic analysis are often taken to be the impetus which gave
rise to morphology as a separate field within generative theory, and which therefore
opened the debate between lexicalist and syntactic analyses of nominalizations. 
31 Conclusion on chapter II.
Nominalizations   of   the   sort   this   chapter   has   discussed,   nominalizations   of
“philosophical   entities,”   have   been   at   the   center   of   philosophical   discussions   for   a
long   time.   The   chapter   has   argued   that   a   new   ontological   category   needs   to   be
acknowledged for nominalizations of modal predicates, the category of modal objects,
which is close to that of attitudinal objects, a category of objects distinct from that of
events   and   states   reflected   in   nominalizations   of   attitude   verbs.   This   chapter   has
distinguished  three different   strategies  with  which nominalizations  introduce  objects
and argued that they are all involved in the introduction of modal objects.
32 CONCLUSION
Nominalizations are words or phrases derived from verbs, adjectives,  or  other
parts of speech that function as nouns in a sentence. They serve the purpose of turning
verbal or adjectival  ideas into noun phrases. The process  of nominalization involves
morphological and syntactical transformations.
Morphologically,   nominalizations   can   be   formed   through   suffixation,
conversion, or compounding. Suffixation involves adding a specific suffix to a word
to create a noun form, such as adding '-tion' to the verb 'educate' to make 'education.'
Conversion,   on   the   other   hand,   involves   changing   the   word's   syntactic   category
without adding any affixes, as in 'the verb to run' becoming 'the run.' Compounding
involves   joining   two   or   more   words   together   to   form   a   new   noun,   like   'football'   or
'blackboard.'
The   morphological   properties   of   nominalizations   include   the   addition   of
prefixes or suffixes, changes in word stress patterns, and alterations in the word's base
form.   For   example,   in   the   nominalization   'information,'   the   suffix   '-tion'   is   added   to
the verb 'inform,' and the stress moves from the second syllable to the third syllable.
Syntactically, nominalizations can function as subjects, objects, or complements in a
sentence.   They   can   also   be   modified   by   articles,   adjectives,   and   possessive
determiners. For example, in the sentence "His dedication to his job was admirable,"
the  nominalization  'dedication'   functions   as  the  subject  complement  and  is   modified
by the possessive determiner 'his.'
In terms of syntactic structures, nominalizations can occur in various positions
within a  sentence.  They  can appear   as  the  head  of   a noun  phrase,   with determiners,
adjectives,   or   prepositional   phrases   modifying   them.   They   can   also   occur   as   the
complement   of   a   preposition,   such   as   in   the   phrase   "the   importance   of   education."
Additionally,   nominalizations   can   function   as   the   subject   or   object   of   a   verb,   as   in
"The discovery of new evidence confirmed the theory."
33 Overall, the morphology of nominalizations involves various ways of forming
noun   forms   from   other   word   categories,   while   the   syntax   of   nominalized
constructions determines their role and position within a sentence.
34 REFERENCE
1. Tashkent: Newspaper Nation’s Word (Xalq So’zi), Desember 10, 2012 [1-3]
2. Harley,   Heidi,   and   Rolf   Noyer.   1999.   “State-of-the-Article:   Distributed
Morphology.” GLOT International, 4 (4): 3–9
3. Moltmann,   Friederike.   2013c.   “Reference   to   Numbers   in   Natural   Language.”
Philosophical Studies, 162 (3): 499–534.
4. Davidson,   Donald.   1967.   “The   Logical   Form   of   Action   Sentences.”   In   The
Logic of Decision and Action, edited by Nicholas Rescher, 81–95.
5. Twardowski, Kazimierz. 1911/1999. “Actions and Products: Some Remarks on
the Borderline of Psychology, Grammar, and Logic.” 103–132.
6. Ulrich,   William.   1976.   “An   Alleged   Ambiguity   in   the   Nominalizations   of
Illocutionary Verbs.” Philosophica, 18: 113–127.
7. Halliday,   M.   A.   K.   (1985):     Introduction   to   Functional   Grammar,   London:
Edward Arnold.
8. Kolln,   M.   and   Funk,   R.   (1998):     Understanding   English   Grammar,   Needham:
Allyn and Bacon.
9. Corson,   D.   (1997).   The   Learning   and   Use   of   Academic   English   Words   [J].
Language Learning, Volume 47, Issue 4, 671-718.
10. Vasylets, Olena. (2017). The Effects of Mode and Task Complexity on Second
Language Production[J]. Language Learning, (2): 394-430. 
11. Aarts, Rian. (2011). Characteristics of Academic Language Register Occurring
in   Caretaker-Child   Interaction:   Development   and   Validation   of   a   Coding
Scheme [J]. Language Learning, 4: 1173- 1221.
12. Vyatkina,   Nina.   (2013).   Specific   Syntactic   Complexity:   Developmental
Profiling of Individuals Based on an Annotated Learner Corpus[J]. The Modern
Language Journal, (S1): 11-30.
13. Lorés-Sanz,   R.   (2016).   ELF   in   the   making?   simplification   and   hybridity   in
abstract writing[J]. Journal of English as a Lingua Franca, 53-81.
35 14. Hyland, Ken. (2017). Is academic writing becoming more informal?[J]. English
for Specific Purposes, (1): 40-51.
15. Levin,   B.,   &   Rappaport   Hovav,   M.   (1988).   Non-event   -er   nominals:   A   probe
into argument structure. Linguistics, 26, 1067–1083.
16. Roeper,   T.   (1987).   Implicit   arguments   and   the   Head-Complement   relation.
Linguistic Inquiry, 18, 267–310.
17. Heyvaert,   L.   (2010).   A   cognitive-functional   perspective   on   deverbal
nominalization in English: Descriptive findings and theoretical ramifications. In
M.   Rathert   &   A.   Alexiadou   (Eds.),   The   semantics   of   nominalizations   across
languages and frameworks (pp. 51–81).
18. Chomsky,   N.   (1970).   Remarks   on   nominalization.   In   R.   Jacobs   &   P.
Rosenbaum   (Eds.),   Readings   in   English   transformational   grammar   (pp.   184–
221).
19. Cohen,   A.   (2016).   A   semantic   explanation   for   the   External   Argument
Generalization. Morphology, 26, 91–103.
20. Booij, G. (1986). Form and meaning in morphology: The case of Dutch “agent
nouns.” Linguistics, 24, 503–517.
36

The syntax nominalization

Купить
  • Похожие документы

  • Analysis of English and Uzbek poetry
  • Sohaga oid matnlar tarjimasidagi muammolar
  • Tarjimaning lingvistik va nolingvistik aspektlari
  • Ilmiy-texnikaviy tarjima
  • Tarjima nazaryasi va amaliyoti tarixi

Подтвердить покупку

Да Нет

© Copyright 2019-2025. Created by Foreach.Soft

  • Инструкция по снятию с баланса
  • Контакты
  • Инструкция использования сайта
  • Инструкция загрузки документов
  • O'zbekcha